back
05 / 06
birds birds birds

Questions on God's Existence and Attributes

October 18, 2021

Summary

Topics include monotheism, the Ontological Argument, and whether God is merely a projection of human desires.

KEVIN HARRIS: Welcome to Reasonable Faith with Dr. William Lane Craig, the podcast of ReasonableFaith.org. I’m Kevin Harris. We’re dealing with the attributes of God. I want to remind you that if you would like to start a Reasonable Faith chapter in your area, you can do it. Great discussions, guest speakers, debates, and so many other things are happening at these chapters. So go to ReasonableFaith.org and find out more about Reasonable Faith chapters as well as how you can partner with us in this ministry. Just go to ReasonableFaith.org. Dr. Craig and I had a chance to sit down recently and discuss some of the questions that we’ve been getting.

Here’s another question:

Dr. Craig, I have a philosophy of religion class this semester with a professor who is head of the student atheist organization club on campus. He writes off all of your arguments for the existence of God because he says they do not even identify half of what he calls the big five attributes of God. The big five are: God is singular, God is personal, he’s all-knowing, all-powerful, and all-good. I know that if he were to come to discover the type of cause discovered by arguments such as the kalam, teleological, and moral argument he would indeed be all-inspired as I am, but still he seems to have a point. Are there any good arguments that warrant a belief in an “omni-God”?

DR. CRAIG: I think that the assumption that this professor is making that is quite mistaken is that in order to prove that something exists you have to show that this thing has all of its essential properties, and I don't think that's true at all. In order to prove that you exist, I can't prove that you have all of the essential properties that you have. For example, one of your essential properties would be being created by God. In order to prove that you exist, would I have to prove that you have the property of “being created by God?” Well, obviously not. So I think that we can say that on the basis of the evidence the best explanation is that there is a creator of the universe, a designer of the universe, a ground of moral value, and so forth, and we don't need to prove that this being is also all-powerful, all-knowing in order to be justified in saying that God exists. And if you do want to be a stickler about this then I'm quite happy to make more modest conclusions. In my own work I've said, for example, that what the kalam cosmological argument proves is that there exists a beginningless, uncaused, spaceless, timeless, immaterial, changeless, enormously powerful, personal creator of the universe, and I'm quite content to rest with that conclusion. If he doesn't want to call such a being God, well that would be a very strange form of atheism indeed to believe that such a being exists. So I'm just not bothered by the fact that the arguments don't issue, for example, in proving that God is all-powerful or that he's all-knowing. What you simply show is that he's enormously powerful (he brings the universe into being out of nothing) or that God is enormously intelligent in that he fine-tuned the universe for life with incomprehensible precision, and that's sufficient to justify, I think, theism. Of course, some of the arguments do give you some of these attributes; for example, that there is one God (we just talked about that), that God is all-good (that's given to you by the moral argument). What was the last – the fifth one?

KEVIN HARRIS: All-powerful and all-knowing.

DR. CRAIG: All-knowing, right! Those two I wouldn't claim to be able to prove unless the ontological argument goes through. Now, if the ontological argument goes through then you've got a maximally great being who does have omnipotence and omniscience and moral perfection in every possible world. So the professor is assuming the ontological argument fails. I think it's a good argument. I think it is sound. So that would give you all of these omni-attributes.

KEVIN HARRIS: This distinguishes arguments for the existence of God that are adequate to show that without showing all these attributes. Then if you want to show that God has these attributes as well you do a little more work. You bring some other things in.

DR. CRAIG: Right. In particular, biblical revelation. Suppose you have good reason to believe that there is an uncaused, spaceless, timeless, immaterial, enormously powerful, personal creator of the universe who is the locus of moral goodness, who has designed the universe, and who raised Jesus of Nazareth from the dead. Well then, you would say, “What else can I know about this being? How has he revealed himself so that I can know him more fully?” And then you discover that he's revealed himself in the history of Israel and in Jesus Christ as an omnipotent and omniscient being who is active in history and so forth. Then you have a full revelation of God. So the professor is asking that we do systematic theology in order to be justified in inferring theism, and I think that's just quite unnecessary.

KEVIN HARRIS: One more question then related since you brought up the ontological argument. Randy writes,

Dr. Craig, I have very much enjoyed your website. My question concerns the ontological argument. I have really favored this argument in its seven step form (I get that at ReasonableFaith.org by the way) or the Alvin Plantinga form as well which, as far as I can tell, is virtually the same. The problem for me arose in negating the first premise, that is: it is possible that a maximally great being does not exist. From this would flow the same premises resulting in the opposite conclusion: Therefore God does not exist. I know this to be false, but I can't put my finger on the fallacy.

He seems to be saying that if you take the first premise of the ontological argument and negate it (“It is possible that a maximally great being does not exist”) then that will lead to the conclusion that God does not exist.

DR. CRAIG: Correct. Right. And there's no fallacy there. This isn't a matter of fallacy. It's just a question of which is true – the first premise or it's negation? Is it true that it's possible that a maximally great being exists or is it true that it's impossible that a maximally great being exists? In other words, it's not a contingent matter whether God exists – either he necessarily exists or he necessarily does not exist. So which do you think is true? At face value, the ontological argument at least shows that if you think it's possible that God exists then God does exist.

KEVIN HARRIS: That's what's amazing about the argument. If it's even possible that God exists then God exists.

DR. CRAIG: Right. If it is possible that he exists then it follows that God exists. So the reader here, Randy, or the person he's talking to just needs to ask himself: Do you think it's possible that God exists? Or do you think that it's impossible that God exists – that it's possible there is no maximally great being? It seems to me that the premise that such a thing is possible is more intuitively obvious and is supported by other theistic arguments as well. I think, in fact, it is not possible that a maximally great being does not exist. It seems to me that that's impossible that a maximally great being not exist, and because it is possible therefore it follows that God exists. So there's no fallacy involved here. The question is just which do you think is true – the first premise or its negation? And it seems to me that both intuitively and through the support of other theistic arguments we have good grounds for thinking the first premise is in fact true.

. . . is to be all-loving. This is a perfection, and therefore to be loving is a moral perfection that God must possess. If that is true then whom are the others that God loves? We know that human beings have not always existed, that they are finite in their existence. Yet, God is essentially loving. He has always been loving. Moreover, human beings are not necessary in their existence. There are possible worlds we can imagine where God alone exists, and there are no human creatures to love. Yet God is essentially loving as a morally perfect being. So whom does he love? Well, the answer is, I think, that in the fellowship of the Trinity the Father loves the Son and the Spirit. The Son loves the Father and the Spirit. The Spirit loves the Father and the Son. In these intra-trinitarian relations you have self-giving love that each individual gives himself away in love to the others.

I think this shows the superiority of a trinitarian concept of God over a unitarian concept like Muslims where there is no one else to love but yourself. Therefore, there is no one to whom one can give one’s love in a unitarian concept of God apart from creating creatures. So I think when we grasp that difference, we can see that God’s being self-giving love is fulfilled within the Trinity itself and has no need of creatures in the way that the unitarian God would in Islam.

What that means, therefore, is that if God does create finite persons whom he loves, this cannot be for God’s sake because God is completely fulfilled in the self-giving love relationships among the members of the Trinity. Whom then is this for, this creation of these finite creatures? The only answer can be: it is for the sake and the benefit of the creatures themselves. God condescends to create finite persons in his image whom he then invites into this inter-trinitarian relationship as adopted sons and daughters of God. He gives us the wonderful privilege of coming into that love relationship that the Trinity itself embodies as his adopted children.

So far from showing a need in God, I think what this shows is God’s wonderful love expressed first and foremost among the members of the Trinity, but then also expressed for our benefit. The chief end of man is to glorify God and to enjoy him forever. It is for our benefit that creatures exist.

KEVIN HARRIS: I am glad you pointed out that God is not lonely because I’ve actually heard sermons that God was lonely in the vast cosmos and he created us and a world and so forth. Terrible theology. The second question is also about God’s attributes. The questioner asks aren’t his omni-attributes contradictory? Isn’t God infinitely tolerant, infinitely forgiving? Well, then, how can he be infinitely just and infinitely forgiving at the same time?

DR. CRAIG: Interestingly enough, this again connects with the Islamic conception of God in contrast to the Christian concept of God. One of the criticisms that I’ve offered of the Muslim concept of God in my debate with Shabir Ally on what must we do to be saved is that in Islam God’s being all-holy and all-just is in fundamental contradiction to God’s being all-compassionate and all-merciful. These cannot both be fulfilled. So if God does forgive sin, as the Muslim claims because he is all-compassionate, his justice must be compromised. Sin is not punished. Sin is not given its just dessert. God simply blinks at sin and chooses to forgive and to be compassionate and merciful and his justice goes unfulfilled. So God is all-compassionate in Islam only at the expense of no longer being all-just.

Now, contrast that with Christianity where you have the notion of the substitutionary atonement of Christ. The justice and the love of God meet at the cross. At the cross, we see the justice of God completely fulfilled as God’s wrath is poured out upon Christ as our sin-bearer and substitute. He bears the penalty for our sin so that God’s justice and the demands of his holiness are completely fulfilled. But at the same time, we see God’s love at the cross in that God himself, in the person of Christ, takes upon the penalty that his own holiness and justice had demanded. Rather than exact it from us, Christ offers to bear that in our place. He gives himself as a voluntary sacrifice out of love for us. So at the cross, we see both the love and the justice of God completely fulfilled. Therefore, it is the cross that allows God to consistently be all-just, all-holy, and yet all-loving and all-forgiving at the same time. These two attributes of God are reconciled at the cross.

KEVIN HARRIS: I often find that people misunderstand or misrepresent the omni-attributes; and that is they tend toward saying God’s omniscience and omnipotence and so on means that he can do absolutely anything, even logical impossibilities. If your God can do absolutely anything, then he didn’t have to put Jesus on the cross. What do we point out in that?

DR. CRAIG: Well, I think we point out that that is a faulty definition of omnipotence. Omnipotence doesn’t mean the ability to do the logically impossible. God can do all things, but in one sense, to make a square circle or a married bachelor is not a thing. There is no such thing. Those are just logically contradictory combinations of words. So God cannot act contrary to his own nature. He cannot sin, he cannot be unholy, he cannot be unloving. God has to act consistently with his own essence. So it is just a faulty concept of omnipotence. The attribute of omnipotence means that God is capable of doing anything which is logically possible for him to do consistent with his own nature. There are some other caveats on that that one might add of a technical, philosophical nature. These are discussed in Thomas Flint and Alfred Freddoso’s paper “Maximal Power”[1] which is reprinted in my anthology Philosophy of Religion for any philosophy students out there who want a more nuanced and philosophically correct definition of omnipotence. But the rough idea is that God can do anything that is logically possible for him to do.

KEVIN HARRIS: We need to get that definition straight in the Christian world and also in the skeptical world so we are not talking past each other when we are talking about that. Here is another question. How do you answer the objection, Dr. Craig, that God is merely a projection of human desire, goals, wants, and needs, and we somehow project that up in the sky as God and then receive it back as grace?

DR. CRAIG: In a sense, all of the theistic arguments that I’ve laid out are refutations of that. You can’t refute these arguments by just saying, well this is all a projection. If you are going to refute the arguments you have to either show there is a logical misstep in the arguments or you have to show one of the premises is unsupported or false. So you can’t refute the kalam cosmological argument or the design argument by just asserting God is a projection. In fact, what that really tries to explain away would be belief in God – that belief in God is the result of a projection. That may very well be the case for some people. It may be that for some people belief in God is a result of a projection. But that is not the interesting question. What we want to know is: is God’s existence something that is purely imaginary or does God actually exist? Then you have got to deal with the arguments that I’ve given. In any case, I think there is quite a different way of looking at the relationship between God and ourselves in terms of being persons and God being personal. Why couldn’t it be the case that rather than God’s being a sort of superhuman person that we have projected to say that God is a personal being who has created finite persons in his image, and that therefore we are reflections of God’s nature? Just as God is personal, so we are personal to a finite degree. So the projection may be just the opposite. It may not be that we are projecting God. It may be, rather, that we are creations of God which reflect his nature and image. I think that is just as plausible and, indeed, given the arguments for God’s existence, I think there is a personal creator and designer of the universe who is the locus of moral value and has brought us into existence.

KEVIN HARRIS: It seems these God-as-projection arguments would be psychological. They would only examine the psychology of a person who believes in God. You don’t determine whether God exists via psychology.

DR. CRAIG: No. Because, after all, you might psychologically project something that turns out to be really there. That just doesn’t answer the objective question. All that says is maybe Susie or Bill’s belief in God is the result of wish fulfillment or projection or guilt complex or whatever neurosis you want to mention. Maybe that is true. Maybe some people do have that psychological factor as the explanation of, as you say, their autobiographical facts of their psychology. But that doesn’t answer the question of the objective existence of this being in any way at all.

KEVIN HARRIS: You said something related to this so-called new definition of atheism. So many of our atheist friends will insist that the definition of atheism is “a lack of belief in God.” You pointed out a couple of things that are related to this, and that is if a person lacks belief in God that only tells you the mental or psychological or personal state of that person. It tells you nothing as to whether God exists.

DR. CRAIG: Right.

KEVIN HARRIS: And it is not a definition of atheism. It might be a definition that a person is applying to themselves.

DR. CRAIG: Right. It is an autobiographical comment about one’s personal psychology – that I lack a belief in God. It is not a view. It is not something that is either true or false. It is just the absence of this particular belief. As I’ve said before, in that sense our cat Muff was an atheist because she lacked belief in God and therefore was in this psychological state. But that says absolutely nothing about the truth or falsity of the proposition that God exists.

KEVIN HARRIS: Boy, I tell you, I cannot get a lot of people to see that, though. They are really hanging on to this definition.

DR. CRAIG: You know why, I think? I think they hang on to this because it excuses them from engaging in the intellectual hard work of trying to justify their position. They don’t have to offer, then, any justification for what they believe. They just say, “I lack this belief.” It is really intellectual laziness. If I lacked the belief that, say, there is gold on Mars, that wouldn’t prove that there is no gold on Mars. Even if there were no evidence that there is gold on Mars, that is not proof that there isn’t gold on Mars. There could well be some gold there and we just haven’t found it yet. So the mere absence of having some belief doesn’t go to prove that the entity in question doesn’t exist. You can’t excuse yourself in that intellectually lazy way from justifying your viewpoint.

KEVIN HARRIS: A lot of good questions come into the website, ReasonableFaith.org. I mentioned some of the criteria that you kind of use at the beginning. Would you like to elaborate on that? What kind of questions are you looking for?

DR. CRAIG: What I am looking for would be questions that would be of interest to people in general. Not too esoteric, but would be something that our general readership would enjoy listening to or reading about. Also, I like to get questions that show some interaction already with what I’ve said about this in my published work or in podcasts. A question where a person just says something like “How do you reconcile divine foreknowledge and human freedom.” That is sort of a non-starter because I’ve addressed that so many times already. I would prefer that someone interact with what has already been written than just start back at square one again. Also, I am looking for variety. I try to vary the questions – one week on the historical Jesus, another on the kalam argument, another on some aspect of Christian doctrine, another week on, say, Christianity and comparative religions. So I do try to mix it up so we don’t get into a rut and talk about the same subject all the time. Those are some of the criteria that I look at in assessing which question I’m going to put on the website each week.[2]

 

[1] Thomas P. Flint and Alfred J. Freddoso, “Maximal Power,” in The Existence and Nature of God, ed. Alfred J. Freddoso (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1983), pp. 81-113. A copy of this can be found at https://www3.nd.edu/~afreddos/papers/mp.htm (accessed October 18, 2021).

[2] Total Running Time: 23:04 (Copyright © 2021 William Lane Craig)